Discrete Structures

Lecture Notes, 10 Sep 2010

Last Update: 13 September 2010

Note: NEW or UPDATED material is highlighted


Note: A username and password may be required to access certain documents. Please contact Bill Rapaport.


Index to all lectures
…Back to previous lecture

  1. "Recursive" Definition of ("Well-Formed" or Grammatically Correct) Proposition:

    1. Base Case:
        Atomic propositions (represented by p, q, r, etc.) are (well-formed (wf), grammatically correct) propositions.

    2. "Recursive" Cases:
        If A, B are (wf, grammatically correct) propositions (either atomic or molecular),
        then:

        1. ¬A
        2. (AB)
        3. (AB)
        4. (AB)
        5. (AB)
        6. (AB)

        are (wf, grammatically correct) "molecular" (or "compound") propositions.

    3. "Closure" clause: Nothing else is a (wf, grammatically correct) proposition.


  2. Computing truth tables for molecular propositions:

    1. Base case: The truth value of an atomic proposition is either T or else it is F.

    2. Recursive case:

      1. The recursive case is based on the Principle of Compositionality:

        The truth value of a molecular proposition depends on (i.e., is a function of) (i.e., is computed from)

        1. the truth values of its "constituent parts"
        2. and its "principal connective"

            Let * be any of the logical connectives.
            Then:
          • The (constituent) parts of (A * B) are A and B.
          • The principal connective of (A * B) is *.

      2. So, to compute the t-val of a molecular proposition of the form (A * B),
          first compute the t-val of A,
          then compute the t-val of B,
          then use the t-val for * to combine these t-vals into the t-val for (A * B).

      3. UPDATED
        How do you compute the t-vals of A and of B?
          If they are molecular, follow rule B
            (but aren't we in the middle of applying rule B?
            Yes!
            This is called a "recursive" application of the rule,
              because the same rule "recurs" (= re-occurs) inside of its own application)

          If they are atomic, then apply the Base Case, rule A:

            the t-val is either T or else F.

    3. UPDATED
      In the t-table for ((p ∨ q) ∧ ¬(p ∧ q)) from last lecture,
        the "input" columns are the tvals of the atomic propositions,
        the "intermediate columns" are the tvals of the constituent parts,
        and the "output" column is the final t-val for the molecular proposition.


  3. Translating from English to Logic:

    1. This is a hard problem, because there are lots of different ways to say the same thing in English;

    2. It is equivalent to the Natural-Language Understanding Problem of computational linguistics:
        How do you represent English sentences so that computers can understand them?

      1. Trivial way: input English sentence S1; output atomic proposition p1
      2. For better ways, see websites, esp. Suber's guide


  4. Propositional Equivalences (§1.2)

    1. Consider the t-table for (p ∨ ¬p)
      (I won't type it in here; you should do it!)

      Note that, for all possible t-vals of its atomic proposition, the t-val of the molecular proposition is T.

    2. Def:
        Let A be a proposition.
        Then A is a tautology
        =def
        for all possible t-vals of A's atomic propositions (i.e., for all rows of A's t-table), t-val(A)=T.

    3. Consider the t-table for (p ∧ ¬p)
      (I won't type it in here; you should do it!)

      Note that, for all possible t-vals of its atomic proposition, the t-val of the molecular proposition is F.

    4. Def:
        Let A be a proposition.
        Then A is a contradiction
        =def
        for all possible t-vals of A's atomic propositions (i.e., for all rows of A's t-table), t-val(A)=F.

    5. Consider the t-table for (pq)
      (I won't type it in here; you should do it!)

      UPDATED
      Note that, there are some possible t-vals of its atomic proposition such that the t-val of the molecular proposition is T,
      but there are some other possible t-vals of its atomic proposition such that the t-val of the molecular proposition is F.

    6. UPDATED
      Def:
        Let A be a proposition.
        Then A is contingent
        =def
        there are some possible t-vals of A's atomic propositions (i.e., there are some rows of A's t-table) such that t-val(A)=T
          (so it's not a contradiction),
        but there are some (other) possible t-vals of A's atomic propositions (i.e., there are some other rows of A's t-table) such that t-val(A)=F
          (so it's not a tautology).

    7. Recall that the input-output columns of the t-table for ((p ∨ q) ∧ ¬(p ∧ q)) matched those of the t-table for (p ⊕ q).

      1. Def:
          Let A, B be propositions.
          Then A is (logically) equivalent to B
          =def
          for all rows of A's and B's t-tables, t-val(A) = t-val(B)

      2. Notation: AB for: A is logically equivalent to B

        • So, we can say:
            ((p ∨ q) ∧ ¬(p ∧ q)) ≡ (p ⊕ q)

        • Note that ≡ is not one of our proposition-forming binary connectives
            (it's not part of the recursive definition of "proposition").
          And "A ≡ B" is not a proposition of propositional logic.
          Instead, it's a sentence of "mathematical English" that is about propositional logic.
Next lecture: the relation between ≡ and ↔…


Text copyright © 2010 by William J. Rapaport (rapaport@buffalo.edu)
Cartoon links and screen-captures appear here for your enjoyment.
They are not meant to infringe on any copyrights held by the creators.
For more information on any cartoon, click on it, or contact me.

http://www.cse.buffalo.edu/~rapaport/191/F10/lecturenotes-20100910.html-20100913