From boulder!ncar!mailrus!tut.cis.ohio-state.edu!bloom-beacon!SAIL.STANFORD.EDU!JMC Mon Nov 7 09:26:34 EST 1988 Article 1818 of comp.ai.digest: Path: sunybcs!boulder!ncar!mailrus!tut.cis.ohio-state.edu!bloom-beacon!SAIL.STANFORD.EDU!JMC >From: JMC@SAIL.STANFORD.EDU (John McCarthy) Newsgroups: comp.ai.digest Subject: AI as CS and the scientific epistemology of the common sense world Date: 1 Nov 88 05:54:00 GMT Sender: daemon@bloom-beacon.MIT.EDU Organization: The Internet Lines: 89 Approved: ailist@ai.ai.mit.edu [In reply to message sent Mon 31 Oct 1988 20:39-EST.] Intelligence can be studied (1) through the physiology of the brain, (2) through psychology, (3) through studying the tasks presented in the achievement of goals in the common sense world. No one of the approaches can be excluded by a priori arguments, and I believe that all three will eventually succeed, but one will succeed more quickly than the other two and will help mop up the other two. I have left out sociology, because I think its contribution will be peripheral. AI is the third approach. It proceeds mainly in computer science departments, and many of its methods are akin to other computer science topics. It involves experimenting with computer programs and sometimes hardware and rarely includes either psychological or physiological experiments with humans or animals. It isn't further from other computer science topics than they are from each other and there are more and more hybrids of AI with other CS topics all the time. Perhaps Simon doesn't like the term AI, because his and Newell's work involves a hybrid with psychology and has involved psychological experiments as well as experimental computer programming. Surely some people should pursue that mixture, which has sometimes been fruitful, but most AI researchers stick to experimental programming and also AI theory. In my opinion the core of AI is the study of the common sense world and how a system can find out how to achieve its goals. Achieving goals in the common sense world involves a different kind of information situation than science has had to deal with previously. This fact causes most scientists to make mistakes in thinking about it. Some pick an aspect of the world that permits a conventional mathematical treatment and retreat into it. The result is that their results often have only a metaphorical relation to intelligence. Others demand differential equations and spend their time rejecting approaches that don't have them. Why does the common sense world demand a different approach? Here are some reasons. (1) Only partial information is available. It is partial not merely quantitatively but also qualitatively. We don't know all the relevant phenomena. Nevertheless, humans can often achieve goals using this information, and there is no reason humans can't understand the processes required to do it well enough to program them in computers. (2) The concepts used in common sense reasoning have a qualitatively approximate character. This is treated in my paper ``Ascribing Mental Qualities to Machines.'' (3) The theories that can be obtained will not be fully predictive of behavior. They will predict only when certain conditions are met. Curiously, while many scientists demand fully predictive theories, when they build digital hardware, they accept engineering specifications that aren't fully predictive. For example, consider a flip-flop with a J input, a K input and a clock input. The manufacturer specifies what will happen if the clock is turned on for long enough and then turned off provided exactly one of the J and K inputs remains high during this period and the other remains low. The specifications do not say what will happen if both are high or both are low or if they change while the clock is turned on. The manufacturer doesn't guarantee that all the flip-flops he sells will behave in the same way under these conditions or that he won't change without notice how they behave. All he guarantees is what will happen when the flip-flop is used in accordance with the ``design rules''. Computer scientists are also quite properly uninterested in non-standard usage. This contrasts with linear circuit theory which in principle tells how a linear circuit will respond to any input function of time. Newtonian and non-relativistic quantum mechanics tell how particles respond to arbitrary forces. Quantum field theory seems to be more picky. Many programs have specified behavior only for inputs meeting certain conditions, and some programming languages refrain from specifying what will happen if certain conditions aren't met. The implementor make the compiler do whatever is convenient or even not figure out what will happen. What we can learn about the common sense world is like what is specified about the flip-flop, only even more limited. Therefore, some people regard the common sense world as unfair and refuse to do science about it.